System L

System L is a natural deductive logic developed by E.J. Lemmon.[1] Derived from Suppes' method,[2] it represents natural deduction proofs as sequences of justified steps. Both methods are derived from Gentzen's 1934/1935 natural deduction system,[3] in which proofs were presented in tree-diagram form rather than in the tabular form of Suppes and Lemmon. Although the tree-diagram layout has advantages for philosophical and educational purposes, the tabular layout is much more convenient for practical applications.

A similar tabular layout is presented by Kleene.[4] The main difference is that Kleene does not abbreviate the left hand sides of assertions to line numbers, preferring instead to either give full lists of precedent propositions or alternatively indicate the left hand sides by bars running down the left of the table to indicate dependencies. However, Kleene's version has the advantage that it is presented, although only very sketchily, within a rigorous framework of metamathematical theory, whereas the books by Suppes[2] and Lemmon[1] are applications of the tabular layout for teaching introductory logic.

Description of the deductive system

The syntax of proof is governed by nine primitive rules:

  1. The Rule of Assumption (A)
  2. Modus Ponendo Ponens (MPP)
  3. The Rule of Double Negation (DN)
  4. The Rule of Conditional Proof (CP)
  5. The Rule of ∧-introduction (∧I)
  6. The Rule of ∧-elimination (∧E)
  7. The Rule of ∨-introduction (∨I)
  8. The Rule of ∨-elimination (∨E)
  9. Reductio Ad Absurdum (RAA)

In system L, a proof has a definition with the following conditions:

  1. has a finite sequence of well-formed formulas (or wffs)
  2. each line of it is justified by a rule of the system L
  3. the last line of the proof is what is intended, and this last line of the proof uses only the premises which were given, if any.

If no premise is given, the sequent is called theorem. Therefore, the definition of a theorem in system L is:

Examples

An example of the proof of a sequent (Modus Tollendo Tollens in this case):

pq, ¬q ⊢ ¬p [Modus Tollendo Tollens (MTT)]
Assumption number Line number Formula (wff) Lines in-use and Justification
1 (1) (pq) A
2 (2) ¬q A
3 (3) p A (for RAA)
1, 3 (4) q 1, 3, MPP
1, 2, 3 (5) q ∧ ¬q 2, 4, ∧I
1, 2 (6) ¬p 3, 5, RAA
Q.E.D

An example of the proof of a sequent (a theorem in this case):

p ∨ ¬p
Assumption number Line number Formula (wff) Lines in-use and Justification
1 (1) ¬(p ∨ ¬p) A (for RAA)
2 (2) p A (for RAA)
2 (3) (p ∨ ¬p) 2, ∨I
1, 2 (4) (p ∨ ¬p) ∧ ¬(p ∨ ¬p) 3, 1, ∧I
1 (5) ¬p 2, 4, RAA
1 (6) (p ∨ ¬p) 5, ∨I
1 (7) (p ∨ ¬p) ∧ ¬(p ∨ ¬p) 1, 6, ∧I
(8) ¬¬(p ∨ ¬p) 1, 7, RAA
(9) (p ∨ ¬p) 8, DN
Q.E.D

Each rule of system L has its own requirements for the type of input(s) or entry(es) that it can accept and has its own way of treating and calculating the assumptions used by its inputs.

History of tabular natural deduction systems

The historical development of tabular-layout natural deduction systems which are rule-based, and which indicate antecedent propositions by line numbers (and related methods such as vertical bars or asterisks) includes the following publications.

See also

Notes

  1. 1 2 See Lemmon 1965 for an introductory presentation of Lemmon's natural deduction system.
  2. 1 2 See Suppes 1999, pp. 25–150, for an introductory presentation of Suppes' natural deduction system.
  3. Gentzen 1934, Gentzen 1935.
  4. Kleene 2002, pp. 50–56, 128–130.
  5. Quine (1981). See particularly pages 91–93 for Quine's line-number notation for antecedent dependencies.
  6. A particular advantage of Kleene's tabular natural deduction systems is that he proves the validity of the inference rules for both propositional calculus and predicate calculus. See Kleene 2002, pp. 44–45, 118–119.

References

External links

This article is issued from Wikipedia - version of the 8/2/2015. The text is available under the Creative Commons Attribution/Share Alike but additional terms may apply for the media files.