Beatty sequence

In mathematics, a Beatty sequence (or homogeneous Beatty sequence) is the sequence of integers found by taking the floor of the positive multiples of a positive irrational number. Beatty sequences are named after Samuel Beatty, who wrote about them in 1926.

Rayleigh's theorem, named after Lord Rayleigh, states that the complement of a Beatty sequence, consisting of the positive integers that are not in the sequence, is itself a Beatty sequence generated by a different irrational number.

Beatty sequences can also be used to generate Sturmian words.

Definition

A positive irrational number generates the Beatty sequence

If then is also a positive irrational number. These two numbers naturally satisfy the equation . The two Beatty sequences they generate,

and
,

form a pair of complementary Beatty sequences. Here, "complementary" means that every positive integer belongs to exactly one of these two sequences.

Examples

For r = the golden mean, we have s = r + 1. In this case, the sequence , known as the lower Wythoff sequence, is

and the complementary sequence , the upper Wythoff sequence, is

These sequences define the optimal strategy for Wythoff's game, and are used in the definition of the Wythoff array

As another example, for r = √2, we have s = 2 + √2. In this case, the sequences are

And for r = π and s = π/(π - 1) the sequences are

Notice that any number in the first sequence is lacking in the second, and vice versa.

History

Beatty sequences got their name from the problem posed in the American Mathematical Monthly by Samuel Beatty in 1926.[1][2] It is probably one of the most often cited problems ever posed in the Monthly. However, even earlier, in 1894 such sequences were briefly mentioned by John W. Strutt (3rd Baron Rayleigh) in the second edition of his book The Theory of Sound.[3]

Rayleigh theorem

The Rayleigh theorem (also known as Beatty's theorem) states that given an irrational number there exists so that the Beatty sequences and partition the set of positive integers: each positive integer belongs to exactly one of the two sequences.[3]

First proof

Given let . We must show that every positive integer lies in one and only one of the two sequences and . We shall do so by considering the ordinal positions occupied by all the fractions j/r and k/s when they are jointly listed in nondecreasing order for positive integers j and k.

To see that no two of the numbers can occupy the same position (as a single number), suppose to the contrary that for some j and k. Then r/s = j/k, a rational number, but also, not a rational number. Therefore, no two of the numbers occupy the same position.

For any j/r, there are j numbers i/rj/r and numbers , so that the position of in the list is . The equation implies

Likewise, the position of k/s in the list is .

Conclusion: every positive integer (that is, every position in the list) is of the form or of the form , but not both. The converse statement is also true: if p and q are two real numbers such that every positive integer occurs precisely once in the above list, then p and q are irrational and the sum of their reciprocals is 1.

Second proof

Collisions: Suppose that, contrary to the theorem, there are integers j > 0 and k and m such that

This is equivalent to the inequalities

For non-zero j, the irrationality of r and s is incompatible with equality, so

which lead to

Adding these together and using the hypothesis, we get

which is impossible (one cannot have an integer between two adjacent integers). Thus the supposition must be false.

Anti-collisions: Suppose that, contrary to the theorem, there are integers j > 0 and k and m such that

Since j + 1 is non-zero and r and s are irrational, we can exclude equality, so

Then we get

Adding corresponding inequalities, we get

which is also impossible. Thus the supposition is false.

Properties

if and only if

where denotes the fractional part of i.e., .

Proof:

Furthermore,

Proof:

Relation with Sturmian sequences

The first difference

of the Beatty sequence associated to the irrational number is a characteristic Sturmian word over the alphabet .

Generalizations

The Lambek–Moser theorem generalizes the Rayleigh theorem and shows that more general pairs of sequences defined from an integer function and its inverse have the same property of partitioning the integers.

Uspensky's theorem states that, if are positive real numbers such that contains all positive integers exactly once, then That is, there is no equivalent of Rayleigh's theorem to three or more Beatty sequences.[4][5]

References

  1. Beatty, Samuel (1926). "Problem 3173". American Mathematical Monthly. 33 (3): 159. doi:10.2307/2300153.
  2. S. Beatty; A. Ostrowski; J. Hyslop; A. C. Aitken (1927). "Solutions to Problem 3173". American Mathematical Monthly. 34 (3): 159–160. doi:10.2307/2298716. JSTOR 2298716.
  3. 1 2 John William Strutt, 3rd Baron Rayleigh (1894). The Theory of Sound. 1 (Second ed.). Macmillan. p. 123.
  4. J. V. Uspensky, On a problem arising out of the theory of a certain game, Amer. Math. Monthly 34 (1927), pp. 516–521.
  5. R. L. Graham, On a theorem of Uspensky, Amer. Math. Monthly 70 (1963), pp. 407–409.

Additional reading

External links

This article is issued from Wikipedia - version of the 11/20/2016. The text is available under the Creative Commons Attribution/Share Alike but additional terms may apply for the media files.