Causality conditions

This article is about the classification of Lorentzian manifolds according to the types of causal structures they admit. For a basic treatment of the possible causal relationships among points in a Lorentzian manifold, including the definitions of terms used in this article, see Causal structure.

In the study of Lorentzian manifold spacetimes there exists a hierarchy of causality conditions which are important in proving mathematical theorems about the global structure of such manifolds. These conditions were collected during the late 1970s.[1]

The weaker the causality condition on a spacetime, the more unphysical the spacetime is. Spacetimes with closed timelike curves, for example, present severe interpretational difficulties. See the grandfather paradox.

It is reasonable to believe that any physical spacetime will satisfy the strongest causality condition: global hyperbolicity. For such spacetimes the equations in general relativity can be posed as an initial value problem on a Cauchy surface.

The hierarchy

There is a hierarchy of causality conditions, each one of which is strictly stronger than the previous. This is sometimes called the causal ladder. The conditions, from weakest to strongest, are:

Given are the definitions of these causality conditions for a Lorentzian manifold . Where two or more are given they are equivalent.

Notation:

(See causal structure for definitions of , and , .)

Non-totally vicious

Chronological

Causal

Distinguishing

Past-distinguishing

Future-distinguishing

Strongly causal

Stably causal

A manifold satisfying any of the weaker causality conditions defined above may fail to do so if the metric is given a small perturbation. A spacetime is stably causal if it cannot be made to contain closed causal curves by arbitrarily small perturbations of the metric. Stephen Hawking showed[2] that this is equivalent to:

Globally hyperbolic

Robert Geroch showed[3] that a spacetime is globally hyperbolic if and only if there exists a Cauchy surface for . This means that:

See also

References

  1. E. Minguzzi and M. Sanchez, The causal hierarchy of spacetimes in H. Baum and D. Alekseevsky (eds.), vol. Recent developments in pseudo-Riemannian geometry, ESI Lect. Math. Phys., (Eur. Math. Soc. Publ. House, Zurich, 2008), pp. 299–358, ISBN 978-3-03719-051-7, arXiv:gr-qc/0609119
  2. S.W. Hawking, The existence of cosmic time functions Proc. R. Soc. Lond. (1969), A308, 433
  3. R. Geroch, Domain of Dependence J. Math. Phys. (1970) 11, 437–449
This article is issued from Wikipedia - version of the 3/12/2016. The text is available under the Creative Commons Attribution/Share Alike but additional terms may apply for the media files.